Book VII of Euclid’s Elements
Mueller [13, p. 11] explains the format of the propositions in the Elements. A usual proposition has the format protasis, ekthesis, diorismos, kataskeuē, apodeixis, and sumperasma. The protasis is the statement of the proposition. The ekthesis instantiates typical objects that are going to be worked with. The diorismos asserts that to prove the proposition it suffices to prove something about the instantiated objects. The kataskeuē constructs things using the instantiated object. The apodeixis proves the claim of the diorismos. The sumperasma asserts that the proposition is proved by what has been done with the instantiated objects.
Netz [14, pp. 268–269]:
The Greeks cannot speak of ‘’. What they must do is to use, effectively, something like a dot-representation: the general set of numbers is represented by a diagram consisting of a definite number of lines. Here the generalisation procedure becomes very problematic, and I think the Greeks realised this. This is shown by their tendency to prove such propositions with a number of numbers above the required minimum. This is an odd redundancy, untypical of Greek mathematical economy, and must represent what is after all a justified concern that the minimal case, being also a limiting case, might turn out to be unrepresentative. The fear is justified, but the case of is only quantitatively different from the case of . The truth is that in these propositions Greek actually prove for particular cases, the generalisation being no more than a guess; arithmeticians are prone to guess.
To sum up: in arithmetic, the generalisation is from a particular case to an infinite multitude of mathematically distinguishable cases. This must have exercised the Greeks. They came up with something of a solution for the case of a single infinity. The double infinity of sets of numbers left them defenceless. I suspect Euclid was aware of this, and thus did not consider his particular proofs as rigorous proofs for the general statement, hence the absence of the sumperasma. It is not that he had any doubt about the truth of the general conclusion, but he did feel the invalidity of the move to that conclusion.
The issue of mathematical induction belongs here.
Mathematical induction is a procedure similar to the one described in this chapter concerning Greek geometry. It is a procedure in which generality is sustained by repeatability. Here the similarity stops. The repeatability, in mathematical induction, is not left to be seen by the well-educated mathematical reader, but is proved. Nothing in the practices of Greek geometry would suggest that a proof of repeatability is either possible or necessary. Everything in the practices of Greek geometry prepares one to accept the intuition of repeatability as a substitute for its proof. It is true that the result of this is that arithmetic is less tightly logically principled than geometry – reflecting the difference in their subject matters. Given the paradigmatic role of geometry in this mathematics, this need not surprise us.
VII, Definitions:
1. An unit is that by virtue of which each of the things that exist is called one. 2. A number is a multitude composed of units. 3. A number is a part of a number, the less of the greater, when it measures the greater; 4. but parts when it does not measure it. 5. The greater number is a multiple of the less when it is measured by the less.
20. Numbers are proportional when the first is the same multiple, or the same part, or the same parts, of the second that the third is of the fourth.
“ is the same part of that is of ” means that as many numbers as there are in equal to , so many numbers are there in equal to . In other words, can be divided into numbers equal to and can be divided into numbers equal to , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of . In other words, whatever multiple is of , the same multiple is of .
“ is the same parts of that is of ” means that there is a part of and a part of such that (i) the part of is the same part of that the part of is of , and (ii) the part of is the same part of that the part of is of . In other words, there is a part of and a part of such that (i) can be divided into numbers equal to the part of and can be divided into numbers equal to the part of , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of , and (ii) is the same part of that is of .
“sum of”
“divided”
“equal”
“same multiple”
VII.5: “If a number be a part of a number, and another be the same part of another, the sum will also be the same part of the sum that the one is of the one.”
Proof.
Let be the same part of that is of . I say that the sum of is also the same part of the sum of that is of .
Say
and
and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of .
Since and , therefore . But, as the multitude of is equal to the multitude of , the sum of can be divided as
and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of . Therefore, whatever multiple is of , the sum of is the same multiple of the sum of . Therefore, whatever part is of , the sum of is the same part of the sum of . ∎
“same parts”
VII.6: “If a number be parts of a number, and another be the same parts of another, the sum will also be the same parts of the sum that the one is of the one.”
Proof.
Let be the same parts of that is of . I say that the sum of is the same parts of the sum of that is of .
Because be the same parts of that is of , there is a part of and a part of such that can be divided as with equal to the part of , and can be divided as with equal to the part of , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of , and is the same part of that is of .
Because is the same part of that is of , therefore is the same part of that the sum of is of the sum of (VII.5).
And, as the multitude of is equal to the multitude of , the sum of can be divided as
where each is equal to the same part of , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of .
Therefore is the same parts of that is of . ∎
transitivity of same part
if is the same part of that it is of , then
VII.7: “If a number be that part of a number, which a number subtracted is of a number subtracted, the remainder will also be the same part of the remainder that the whole is of the whole.”
Proof.
Let be the same part of that is of . I say that is the same part of that is of .
Let be such that is the same part of that is of .
Because is the same part of that is of , it follows that is the same part of that is of (VII.5). But and , so is the same part of that is of .
But by hypothesis, is the same part of that is of . Therefore is the same part of that it is of , and therefore . Subtract from and ; Then , i.e. .
By construction of , is the same part of that is of . And . Therefore is the same part of that is of . But by hypothesis, is the same part of that is of . Therefore is the same part of that is of . ∎
VII.8: “If a number be the same parts of a number that a number subtracted is of a number subtracted, the remainder will also be the same parts of the remainder that the whole is of the whole.”
Proof.
Let be the same parts of that is of . I say that is the same parts of that is of .
Let be made equal to . So is the same parts of that is of . This means that there is a part of and a part of such that can be divided as where each is equal to the part of , and can be divided as where each is equal to the part of , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of , and is the same part of that is of .
Because is the same part of that is of while is greater than , therefore is greater than . Let be made equal to . Thus is the same part of that is of . Therefore the remainder is the same part of that is of (VII.7).
Each is equal to the same part of . And the multitude of is equal to the multitude of . Therefore is the same parts of that is of .
. But . So . Then
And , therefore is the same parts of that is of . ∎
Uses VII.5,6 for arbitrarily many terms
VII.9: “If a number be a part of a number, and another be the same part of another, alternately also, whatever part or parts the first is of the third, the same part, or the same parts, will the second also be of the fourth.”
Proof.
Let be the same part of that is of . I say that, alternately also, is the same part or parts of that is of .
Since is the same part of that is of , can be divided into numbers equal to , can be divided into numbers equal to , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of . Because and for each and , whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is of . Therefore whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is the sum of of the sum of (VII.5, 6). That is, whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is of .
But and , so whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is of . ∎
VII.10: “If a number be parts of a number, and another be the same parts of another, alternately also, whatever parts or part the first is of the third, the same parts or the same part will the second also be of the fourth.”
Proof.
Let be the same parts of that is of . I say that, alternately also, is the same part or parts of that is of .
Because is the same parts of that is of , there is a part of and a part of such that can be divided as with each equal to the part of , and can be divided as with each equal to the part of , and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of .
Since is the same part of that is of , alternately also, is the same part or parts of that is of (VII.9).
Therefore whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is the sum of of the sum of (VII.5, 6). But is the same part or parts of that is of and , , therefore whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is of . ∎
“ is to as is to ”
VII.11: “If, as whole is to whole, so is a number subtracted to a number subtracted, the remainder will also be to the remainder as whole to whole.”
Proof.
Let be to as is to . I say that is to as is to .
Since as is to so is to , is the same part or parts of that is of (VII, Definition 20). Therefore the remainder is the same part or parts of the remainder that is of (VII.7, 8).
Therefore, as is to , so is to (VII, Definition 20). ∎
“antecedent”, “consequent”
VII.12: “If there be as many numbers as we please in proportion, then, as one of the antecedents is to one of the consequents, so are all the antecedents to all the consequents.”
Proof.
Let be as many numbers as we please in proportion, so that as is to so is to . I say that, as is to , so is to .
Since, as is to so is to , whatever part or parts is of the same part or parts is of . Therefore the sum of is the same part or parts of the sum of that is of (VII.5, 6).
Therefore, as is to , so are to (VII, Definition 20). ∎
VII.13: “If four numbers be proportional, they will also be proportional alternately.”
Proof.
Let be proportional, so that as is to , so is to . I say that they are also proportional alternately, that is, that as is to , so is to .
Since is to as is to , whatever part or parts is of , the same part or parts is of (VII, Definition 20). Therefore, alternately, whatever part or part is of , the same part or parts is of (VII.10). Therefore, as is to , so is to (VII, Definition 20). ∎
“same ratio”
transitivity of same ratio
VII.14: “If there be as many numbers as we please, and others equal to them in multitude, which taken two and two are in the same ratio, they will also be in the same ratio ex aequali.”
Proof.
Let there be as many numbers as we please and others equal to them in multitude which when taken two and two are in the same ratio, so that as is to so is to . I say that, ex aequali, as is to so is to .
Since as is to so is to , therefore, alternately, as is to , so is to (VII.13). Likewise, as is to , so is to , etc., and because is to , so is to , then as is to , so is to . And so on. Thus as is to , so is to . Therefore, alternately, is to , so is to (VII.13). ∎
“measures the same number of times”
cf. VII.8.
VII.15: “If an unit measure any number, and another number measure any other number the same number of times, alternately also, the unit will measure the third number the same number of times that the second measures the fourth.”
Proof.
Let the unit measure any number and let another number measure any other number the same number of times. I say that, alternately also, the unit measures the number the same number of times that measures .
Since the unit measures the number the same number of times that measures , therefore, as many units as there are in , so many numbers equal to are there in also. Let be divided into the units in it, , and let and be divided into the numbers in it equal to . Thus the multitude of is equal to the multitude of .
Because the units are equal to one another, and the numbers are equal to one another, and the multitude of the units is equal to the multitude of the numbers , therefore, as is to so is to . Therefore, as one of the antecedents is to one of the consequents, so are all the antecedents to all the consequents (VII.12). All the antecedents are , and all the consequents are , so as the unit is to the number , so is to . But the unit is equal to the unit and the number is equal to the number . Therefore, as the unit is to the number , so is to . Therefore, the unit measures the number the same number of times that measures . ∎
VII, Definitions:
11. A prime number is that which is measured by an unit alone. 12. Numbers prime to one another are those which are measured by an unit alone as a common measure. 13. A composite number is that which is measured by some number. 14. Numbers composite to one another are those which are measured by some number as a common measure. 15. A number is said to multiply a number when that which is multiplied is added to itself as many times as there are units in the other, and thus some number is produced.
“ measures according to the units in ”
VII.16: “If two numbers by multiplying one another make certain numbers, the numbers so produced will be equal to one another.”
Proof.
Let be two numbers and let by multiplying make , and by multiplying make . I say that .
Since by multiplying has made , therefore measures according to the units in . But the unit also measures the number according to the units in ; therefore, the unit measures the same number of times that measures . Therefore, alternately, the unit measures the same number of times that measures (VII.15).
Again, since by multiplying has made , therefore measures according to the units in . But the unit also measures according to the units in ; therefore the unit measures the same number of times that measures .
But the unit also measures the same number of times that measures . Therefore measures each of the numbers the same number of times. Therefore . ∎
VII.17: “If a number by multiplying two numbers make certain numbers, the numbers so produced will have the same ratio as the numbers multiplied.”
Proof.
Let the number by multiplying the two numbers make . I say that, as is to , so is to .
Since by multiplying has made , therefore measures according to the units in . But the unit also measures the number according to the units in ; therefore the unit measures the number the same number of times that measures . Therefore, as the unit is to the number , so is to (VII, Definition 20).
For the same reason, as the unit is to the number , so is to . Therefore, as is to , so is to . Therefore, alternately, as is to , so is to (VII.13). ∎
VII.18: “If two numbers by multiplying any number make certain numbers, the numbers so produced will have the same ratio as the multipliers.”
Proof.
Let two numbers by multiplying any number make . I say that as is to , so is to .
Since by multiplying has made , therefore also by multiplying has made (VII.16). For the same reason, since by multiplying has made , therefore also by multiplying has made .
Therefore, the number by multiplying the two numbers has made . Therefore, as is to , so is to (VII.17). ∎
VII.19: “If four numbers be proportional, the number produced from the first and fourth will be equal to the number produced from the second and third; and, if the number produced from the first and fourth be equal to that produced from the second and third, the four numbers will be proportional.”
Proof.
Let be four numbers in proportion, so that as is to , so is to ; and let by multiplying make , and let by multiplying make . I say that .
Let by multiplying make . Since by multiplying has made , and by multiplying has made , the number multiplying the two numbers has made . Therefore, as is to , so is to (VII.17).
But by hypothesis as is to , so is to ; therefore as is to , so is to .
Since by multiplying has made but also by multiplying has made , the two numbers by multiplying a certain number have made . Therefore as is to , so is to (VII.18). But further, as is to , so is to ; therefore, as is to , so is to . Therefore has to each of the numbers the same ratio; therefore .
Again, let . I say that, as is to , so is to . With the same construction, since , as is to so is to . But as is to so is to (VII.17), and as is to so is to (VII.18). Therefore, as is to , so is to , and as is to so is to , so as is to , so is to . ∎
VII.20: “The least numbers of those which have the same ratio with them measure those which have the same ratio the same number of times, the greater the greater and the less the less.”
Proof.
Let be the least numbers of those which have the same ratio with . I say that measures the same number of times that measures .
Now, is not parts of . For, if possible, let it be so. Since is to as is to , therefore is to so is to (VII.13). Therefore is the same parts of that is of (VII, Definition 20). Therefore there is a part of such that can be divided into numbers each equal to this part, there is a part of such that can be divided into numbers each equal to this part, the multitude is equal to the multitude of , and each is the same part of that is of . Since the numbers and are equal to one another, and the numbers and are equal to one another, and the multitude of is equal to the multitude of , then as is to so is to . Thus as one of the antecedents is to one of the consequents, so are all the antecedents to all the consequents (VII.12). But and ; therefore, as is to so is to . Therefore are in the same ratio as , being less than them; this is impossible because by hypothesis are the least numbers of those which have the same ratio as them.
Therefore is not parts of . Therefore is part of (VII.4). But as is to so is to , therefore as is to so is to (VII.12). Therefore is the same part of that is of (VII, Definition 20). Therefore measures the same number of times that measures . ∎
“least numbers”
“as many times as measures , so many units let there be in ”
VII.21: “Numbers prime to one another are the least of those which have the same ratio with them.”
Proof.
Let be numbers prime to one another. I say that are the least of those which have the same ratio with them.
If not, there will be some numbers less than which are [the least numbers] in the same ratio with . Let them be . But the least numbers of those which have the same ratio measure those which have the same ratio the same number of times, the greater the greater and the less the less, that is, the antecedent the antecedent and the consequent the consequent (VII.20). Therefore measures the same number of times that measures .
As many times as measures , so many units let there be in . Therefore also measures according to the units in .
And since measures according to the units in , therefore also measures according to the units in (VII.16). For the same reason, also measures according to the units in (VII.16). Therefore measures which are prime to one another: which is impossible (VII, Definition 12).
Therefore there will be no numbers less than which are in the same ratio with .
Therefore are the least of those which have the same ratio with them. ∎
VII.22: “The least numbers of those which have the same ratio with them are prime to one another.”
Proof.
Let be the least of those numbers which have the same ratio with them. I say that are prime to one another.
If they are not prime to one another, some number will measure them.
Let some number measure them, and let it be . And as many times as measures , so many units let there be in , and as many times as measures , so many units let there be in .
Since measures according to the units in , therefore by multiplying has made (VII, Definition 15). For the same reason also, by multiplying has made (VII, Definition 15). Thus, the number multiplying the two numbers has made ; therefore, as is to , so is to (VII.17); therefore are in the same ratio with , being less than : which is impossible.
Therefore, no number will measure the numbers .
Therefore are prime to one another. ∎
VII.23: “If two numbers be prime to one another, the number which measures the one of them will be prime to the remaining number.”
Proof.
∎
VII.24: “If two numbers be prime to any number, their product also will be prime to the same.”
Proof.
∎
VII.25: “If two numbers be prime to one another, the product of one of them into itself will be prime to the remaining one.”
Proof.
∎
VII.26: “If two numbers be prime to two numbers, both to each, their products also will be prime to one another.”
Proof.
∎
Domninus of Larissa, Encheiridion 20–31 [17, pp. 111–115]:
20. Every number, when compared to an arbitrary number with regard to the multitude of monads in them, is either equal to it, or unequal. If they are equal to one another, their relationship to one another will be unique and not further distinguishable. For in the case of equality, one thing cannot be in this fashion and the other thing in that fashion, since what is equal is equal in one single and the same way. If, however, they are unequal, ten different relationships can be contemplated concurrently.
21. But before giving an account of these, we must state that it is true for every pair of numbers that the lesser is either a part, or parts, of the greater number, since, if it measures the greater one, it is a part of the greater number, such as in the case of 2 which measures 4 and 6, of which it is a half or a third part, respectively. If it does not measure it, it is parts of it, such as in case of 2, which, not measuring 3, is two thirds of it, or in the case of 9, which, not measuring 15, is three fifths of it.
22. Having stated this as a preliminary, we say that if those two numbers which lie before us for inspection are unequal, the lesser either measures the greater, or it does not.
23. If it measures it, the greater number is a multiple of the lesser one, and the lesser number is a submultiple of the greater one, as in the case of 3 and 9, since 9 is a multiple of 3, being its triple, and 3 is a submultiple of 9, being its subtriple.
24. If it does not measure the greater number, and if one subtracts it from it once or several times, it will leave behind something less than itself whch will, by necessity, be either a part, or parts, of the number. For it will leave behind either a monad or some number.
25. If it leaves behind a monad, it obviously leaves behind a part of itself. For the monad is part of every number, since every number is a combination of monads.
26. If it leaves behind some number, it will be either a part of itself, or parts. For it is true for every pair of numbers that the lesser is either a part, or parts, of the greater.
27. Now then, if the lesser number is subtracted once from the greater, and it leaves behind a number less than itself which is a part of it, then the greater number will be superparticular to the lesser, while the lesser number will be subsuperparticular to the greater, as in the case of 2 and 3. For 3 is superparticular to 2, since it includes it and a half of it (therefore, it is also called sesquialter of it), while 2 is subsesquialter to 3. And the same is the case with 6 and 8, as 8 is sesquitertian to 6, while 6 is subsesquitertian to 8.
28. If the remainder is parts of the lesser number, then the greater number will be superpartient, while the lesser number will be subsuperparticular to the greater, as in the case of 3 and 5. For 5 is superpartient to 3, since it includes it and two thirds of it (therefore, it is also called superbitertian of it), while 3 is subsuperbitertian to 5. And the same is the case with 15 and 24, as 24 is supertriquantan of 15, since it includes it and three fifths of it, while 15 is subsupertriquintan of 24.
29. If the lesser number is subtracted more often than once from the greater, and it leaves behind a number less than itself which is part of it, then the greater number will be multiple-superparticular, while the lesser number will be submultiple-superparticular to the greater, as in the case of 2 and 5. For 5 is multiple-superparticular to 2, since it includes it twice and a half of it (therefore, it is also called duplex-sesquialter of it), while 2 is subduplex-sesquialter to 5. And the same is the case with 6 and 26, as 26 is quadruplex-sesquitertian to 6, while 6 is subquadruplex-sesquitertian to 26.
30. If the remainder is parts of the lesser number, then the greater number is multiple-superpartient, while the lesser number is submultiple-superpartient to the greater, as in the case of 3 and 8. For 8 is duplex-superbitertian to 3, while 3 is subduplex-superbitertian to 8. And the same is the case with 10 and 34, as 34 is triplex-superbiquintan of 10, while 10 is subtriplex-superbiquintan of 34.
31. And these are the so-called ten relationships of inequality, to which the ancients also referred as ratios:
- 1.
multiple,
- 2.
submultiple,
- 3.
superparticular,
- 4.
subsuperparticular,
- 5.
superpartient,
- 6.
subsuperpartient,
- 7.
multiple-superparticular,
- 8.
submultiple-superparticular,
- 9.
multiple-superpartient,
- 10.
submultiple-superpartient.
This is the theory of numbers with regard to one another according to the multitude underlying them.
Nicomachus [4]
Theon [5]
Szabó [19] assembles a philological argument that the Euclidean algorithm was created as part of the Pythagorean theory of music. Szabó [19, p. 136, Chapter 2.8] summarizes, “More precisely, this method was developed in the course of experiments with the monochord and was used originally to ascertain the ratio between the lengths of two sections on the monochord. In other words, successive subtraction was first developed in the musical theory of proportions.” Earlier in this work Szabó [19, pp. 28–29] says, “Euclidean arithmetic is predominantly of musical origin not just because, following a tradition developed in the theory of music, it uses straight lines (originally ‘sections of a string’) to symbolize numbers, but also because it uses the method of successive subtraction which was developed originally in the theory of music. However, the theory of odd and even clearly derives from an ‘arithmetic of counting stones’ (ψη̃φοι), which did not originally contain the method of successive subtraction.”
Jordanus Nemorarius, De elementis arithmetice artis [3]
Jordanus Nemorarius, De elementis arithmetice artis [6]
Jordanus Nemorarius, De elementis arithmetice artis II [18, p. 697]:
What we call the denomination of a ratio, at least of a smaller number to a greater, is the part or parts that the smaller is of the greater; and of a greater number to a smaller, the number by which it contains it and the part or parts of the smaller that remain in the greater.
Denominatio dicitur proportionis minoris quidem ad maiorem pars vel partes quote illius fuerit, maioris vero ad minus numerus secundum quem eum continet et pars vel partes minoris que in maiore superfluunt.
Barker [1]
van der Waerden [24, p. 113]: VII.1,2,3, 4–10, 11–19, 20, 21, 22, 24, 26, 27, 33, VIII.2,3,7,8.
Burkert [2]
Philolaus [10]
Archytas [9]
Vitrac [23, p. 305]
Heath [7]
Vandoulakis [22]
Knorr [12, p. 212]
Knorr [12, p. 244]
To Theaetetus, then, we ascribe inter alia these contributions: the discovery of general theorems and classifications in the area of incommensurability; the organization of the fundaments of arithmetic in a systematic and rigorous way as the necessary prelude to those theorems. This effectively places the composition of Elements VII with Theaetetus, but it is clear that much of that work was based on techniques commonplace in the practical computation with fractions: the division algorithm, the properties of ratios of integers. and so on. Theaetetus’ innovations here were the theoretical use of the division algorithm. the devising of sequences of theorems framed around an explicit definition of numerical proportionality (VII, Def. 20). the establishment of a new geometric representation for numbers, contrasting with the older dot-methods. and the discovery and proof of the fundamental theorems on relative primes. (VII.21–28).
Itard [11]
Heiberg [8]
Taisbak [20]
Pengelley and Richman [15]
Pengelley [16]
Witelo [21, p. 47], Definitions:
The quantity which, if multiplied by the smaller, produces the larger or which divides the larger to yield the smaller is called the “denomination of the ratio of the first to the second”. A ratio is said to be compounded of two ratios whenever the denomination of that ratio is produced by multiplying the denominations of those two ratios, [namely] of one into the other.
Aristotle, Metaphysics V.15, 1020-1.
Aristotle, Nicomachean Ethics V.3, 1131a,b.
The just, then, is a species of the proportionate (proportion being not a property only of the kind of number which consists of abstract units, but of number in general). For proportion is equality of ratios, and involves four terms at least (that discrete proportion involves four terms is plain, but so does continuous proportion, for it uses one term as two and mentions it twice; e.g. ‘as the line is to the line , so is the line to the line ’; the line , then, has been mentioned twice, so that if the line be assumed twice, the proportional terms will be four); and the just, too, involves at least four terms, and the ratio between one pair is the same as that between the other pair; for there is a similar distinction between the persons and between the things. As the term , then, is to , so will be to , and therefore, alternando, as is to , will be to . Therefore also the whole is in the same ratio to the whole; and the distribution pairs them in this way, and if they are so combined, pairs them justly. The conjunction, then, of the term with and of with is what is just in distribution, and this species of the just is intermediate, and the unjust is what violates the proportion; for the proportional is intermediate, and the just is proportional. (Mathematicians call this kind of proportion geometrical; for it is in geometrical proportion that it follows that the whole is to the whole as either part is to the corresponding part.) This proportion is not continuous; for we cannot get a single term standing for a person and a thing.
Campanus
(xii) Pars est numerus numeri minor
Peletarius
Billingsley, The elements of geometrie
Forcadel
Zamberti
Jean Errard, Les neuf premiers livres des élémens d’Euclide,
Denis Henrion, Les quinze livres des Elements d’Euclide
Robert Simson, The Elements of Euclid, pp. 253–254 proves that proportion is equivalent in Books V and VII.
Clavius
Tartaglia
Commandinus, Euclidis Elementorum libri XV, p. 87
References
- [1] (2004) Greek musical writings, volume II: harmonic and acoustic theory. Cambridge Readings in the Literature of Music, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [2] (1972) Lore and science in ancient Pythagoreanism. Harvard University Press. Note: Translated from the German by Edwin L. Minar, Jr. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [3] (1991) Jordanus de Nemore, De elementis arithmetice artis: a medieval treatise on number theory. Part I: Text and paraphrase. Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [4] (1926) Nicomachus of Gerasa: Introduction to arithmetic. University of Michigan Studies, Humanistic Series, Vol. XVI, Macmillan, New York. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [5] (1892) Théon de Smyrne, philosophe platonicien. Exposition des connaissances mathématiques utiles pour la lecture de Platon. Librairie Hachette et Cie, Paris. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [6] E. Grant (Ed.) (1974) A source book in medieval science. Harvard University Press. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [7] (1956) The thirteen books of Euclid’s Elements, volume II: Books III-IX. second edition, Dover Publications. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [8] J. L. Heiberg (Ed.) (1884) Euclidis Opera omnia. Euclidis Elementa. Vol. II. Libros V–IX continens. B. G. Teubner, Lipsiae. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [9] (2005) Archytas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, philosopher and mathematician king. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [10] (2006) Philolaus of Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [11] (1961) Les livres arithmétiques d’Euclide. Histoire de la Pensée, Vol. X, Hermann, Paris. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [12] (1975) The evolution of the Euclidean Elements: a study of the theory of incommensurable magnitudes and its significance for early Greek geometry. Synthese Historical Library, Vol. 15, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements, Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [13] (2006) Philosophy of mathematics and deductive structure in Euclid’s Elements. Dover Publications. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [14] (1999) The shaping of deduction in Greek mathematics: a study in cognitive history. Ideas in Context, Vol. 51, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [15] (2006) Did Euclid need the Euclidean algorithm to prove unique factorization?. Amer. Math. Monthly 113 (3), pp. 196–205. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [16] (2013) Quick, does equal ? A mathematician’s secret from Euclid to today. Amer. Math. Monthly 120 (10), pp. 867–876. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [17] (2013) Domninus of Larissa: Enchiridion and spurious works. Mathematica graeca antiqua, Vol. 2, Fabrizio Serra editore. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [18] (2009) The transmission of the Elements to the Latin West: three case studies. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics, E. Robson and J. Stedall (Eds.), pp. 687–706. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [19] (1978) The beginnings of Greek mathematics. Synthese Historical Library, Vol. 17, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht. Note: Translated from the German by A. M. Ungar Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [20] (1971) Division and logos: a theory of equivalent couples and sets of integers, propounded by Euclid in the arithmetical books of the Elements. Acta Historica Scientiarum Naturalium et Medicinalium, Vol. 25, Odense University Press. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [21] (1977) Witelonis Perspectivae liber primus. Book I of Witelo’s Perspectiva. Studia Copernicana, Vol. XV, Ossolineum, The Polish Academy of Sciences Press, Wrocław. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [22] (1998) Was Euclid’s approach to arithmetic axiomatic?. Oriens-Occidens. Sciences, mathématiques et philosophie de l’Antiquité à l’Âge classique (2), pp. 141–181. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [23] (1994) Euclide d’Alexandrie. Les Éléments. Volume 2: Livres V–IX. Bibliothèque d’histoire des sciences, Presses Universitaires de France, Paris. Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.
- [24] (1961) Science awakening. Oxford University Press. Note: Translated by Arnold Dresden Cited by: Book VII of Euclid’s Elements.