Zeno of Elea, locomotion, infinity, and time
1 Generalities
Barnes [11] on Zeno
2 Philology
kinesis is “motion”, “movement”, “change”. But before Aristotle kinesis means more locomotion or disturbance than general change.
3 Mathematics
Heath [96, pp. 271–283]
Szabó [222]
4 Pythagoreans
Guthrie [88]
Horky [102]
Archytas of Tarentum on geometric proportion [103]
Philolaus of Croton [104]
Burkert [25, pp. 285–288]
5 Xenophanes
Testimonia on Fragment 26 from the peripatetic On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias [126, pp. 204–210]
6 Heraclitus
Heraclitus saying things are and are not is like saying that things are specified by their position and velocity, not just position. (A photo does not tell you everything about an object.)
Cornford [43, p. 184]: time is Heraclitus’s primary substance. Ap. Sextus Empiricus, Adv. Math. x.216
7 Parmenides and Melissus
The testimonia, A section of Diels and Kranz, on Parmenides are translated in Gallop [75].
Mourelatos [158, pp. 118–119]
Parmenides criticizes motion in B8.26–33, and Melissus in B7.7–10.
Melissus 4: “Nothing that has a beginning and an end is either everlasting or infinite.” [68, p. 48]. DK30B4.
Palmer [175]
8 Zeno
Zeno [125, pp. 45, 67, 71–85]
Waterfield [249]
Four fragments arguing that if Things are Many a contradiction follows [68, p. 47]. DK29B.
Algra [4]
Guthrie [89]
Solmsen [211, p. 18]
Lloyd [133]
9 Anaxagoras
Fragment 3: “Nor of the small is there a smallest, but always a smaller (for what-is cannot not be) – but also of the large there is always a larger. And [the large] is equal to the small in extent, but in relation to itself each thing is both large and small.” Curd [49, pp. 38–42]
Schofield [195, Chapter 3]
10 Democritus
Democritus DK68B155: “If a cone were cut with a plane parallel to the base, …” [68, p. 106]
Lura [138]
Fragments in Taylor [225]
11 Empedocles
12 Protagoras
Protagoras of Abdera DK80B7: tangents to circles [68, p. 126].
13 Gorgias
Gorgias of Leontini DK82B3: nothing exists, sophisticated argument [68, p. 128]
14 Antiphon the Sophist
Infinite divisibility. Fragments 1, 13 [177]
15 Diogenes of Apollonia
16 Plato
Friedländer [69]
Taylor [224]
Cornford Parmenides [42]
Cornford Timaeus [41]
Plato refers to Zeno making his audience think that things are one and many and at rest and at motion in Phaedrus 261d and Parmenides 129e.
Plato’s Parmenides [5, pp. 93–98, 250–260]
Cornford [43, p. 160] refers to Timaeus 39b, and writes “Distance in space is measurable psychologically, by expenditure of strength; but time-distance can be measured only by counting the rhythmical repitition of the same occurrence.”
Cornford [43, p. 131]: the soul can move itself. Laws 896a. Cornford cites Aetius and Sextus Empiricus.
17 Aristotle
Peripatetic On indivisible lines and On Melissus, Xenophanes, and Gorgias [100]
Heath [98]
Ross [187, p. 94]
Roark [185]
Bolotin [17]
Cherniss [33]
Aristotle De anima, Polansky [178, p. 96]
Aristotle Physics 239b9–14.
Aristotle Prior Analytics 65b16–21.
18 Aristoxenus fl. 335 BC
19 Heraclides Ponticus c. 390 BC–c. 310 BC
Sharples [205]
20 Xenocrates c. 396/395 – c. 314/313 BC
Sambursky [191, p. 91]
Dillon [56, pp. 111ff]: indivisible lines.
21 Theophrastus of Eresus c. 371 BC – c. 287 BC
, Sharples [203]
22 Praxiphanes fl. c. 300 BC
Sharples [207]
23 Strato of Lampsacus c. 335 BC – c. 269 BC
Sharples [206]
24 Eudemus of Rhodes c. 370 BC – c. 300 BC
Sharples [204]
Wehlri fragments 37, 60, 62 and 78 [251].
25 Diodorus Cronus died c. 284 BC
Gaskin [76, pp. 60, 64, 108, 252, 260]
26 Archimedes c. 287 BC – c. 212 BC
Heath [95]
Dijksterhuis [54]
27 Plutarch c. 46 – c. 120
Moralia, book XIII, De communibus notitiis adversus Stoicos [34]
28 Epicurus 341 BC – 270 BC
Letter to Herodotus 57, 61–62. In 38, Epicirus says that there must be a void lest things not move.
Vlastos [242]
Milton [154]
29 Chrysippus c. 279 BC – c. 206 BC
Gould [82, pp. 112–119, chapter V, §1f]
Bobzien [16]
30 Polybius c. 200 BC – c. 118 BC
Histories, Book IV, Chapter 40: “For given infinite time and basins that are limited in volume, it follows that they will eventually be filled, even if silt barely trickles in. After all, it is a natural law that, if a finite quantity goes on and on increasing or decreasing – even if, let us suppose, the amounts involved are tiny – the process will necessarily come to an end at some point within the infinite extent of time.”
31 Asclepiades of Bithynia c. 129/124 BC – 40 BC
Vallance [239]
32 Antiochus of Ascalon c. 125 BC – c. 68 BC
Dillon [55, p. 82]: “there exists nothing whatever in the nature of things that is an absolute least, incapable of division.” Acad. Post. 27ff.
33 Varro 116 BC – 27 BC
Sedley [198]
34 Cicero 106 BC – 43 BC
De natura deorum, I.xxiiii.55: no such thing as an indivisible body
Dillon [56, p. 170]: matter is “capable of infinite section and division”.
Academica, I.vii.27: matter and space are infinitely divisible. Antiochus of Ascalon, in Cicero’s Academica 1.27 [21, p. 98]:
But underlying everything there is a kind of ‘matter’, they think, without any form, and lacking any of those qualities (let’s keep using this term and make it more familiar and gentler on the ear). Everything has been produced or brought about from this, because matter as a whole can receive everything and change in every way and in every part. Matter thus ‘perishes’ into its parts rather than into nothing; and these parts can be infinitely cut or divided since there is no smallest unit in the nature of things, i.e., nothing that can’t be divided. Moreover, everything that is moved is moved through intervals, and these intervals can likewise be infinitely divided.
35 Posidonius c. 135 BC – c. 51 BC
Fragment 98 [111, pp. 395–403]
36 Lucretius c. 99 BC – c. 55 BC
Lucretius De rerum natura 2.238–2.239 [137].
37 Philo of Alexandria c. 25 BC – c. 50
Goodenough [80, pp. 127–139]
38 Alexander of Aphrodisias fl. c. 200
Ancient Commentators on Aristotle
39 Galen 129–c. 200/216
40 Sextus Empiricus c. 160–210
Against the Physicists [12]
Adversus mathematicos I: Against the grammarians [15, pp. 8, 61, 166]
Outlines of Scepticism [6]
Hankinson [91] on moments of time, and on bodies and surfaces in space.
41 Numenius of Apamea fl. c. 150
Numenius [87, p. 58]: “Bodies, containing nothing unchangeable, are naturally subject to change, to dissolution, and to infinite divisions.”
42 Plotinus c. 204/205–270
Wagner [246]
Wallis [247]
Whittaker [254]
Graeser [83]
43 Dionysius of Alexandria c. 200 – 264
Cleve [37]
44 Porphyry 234–c. 305
Gaiser [72, p. 482]. Simplicius, In Physicorum, 454, 6, quotes Porphyry. Take a definite length one cubit long. Divide it in half. Leave one-half undivided and divide the other again. If we continue dividing, Porphyry says that “there is a certain infinite nature enclosed in the cubit, or rather several infinities, one proceeding to the great and one to the small.” The infinitely large is the increasing number of segments.
45 Iamblichus c. 245–c. 325
The Theology of Arithmetic, “On the Dyad” [248, p. 45]: “length is both infinitely divisible and infinitely extensible.”
46 Eusebius 260/265–339/340
Praeparatio evangelica, book XV, chapter XXII: “But in fact the whole sentient is one: for how could it be divided? For there can be no correspondence of equal to equal, because the ruling faculty cannot be equal to each and every sensible object. Into how many parts then shall the division be made? Or shall it be divided into as many parts as the number of varieties in the object of sense that enters? And so then each of those parts of the soul will also perceive by its subdivisions, or the parts of the subdivisions will have no perception; but that is impossible. And if any part perceive all the object, since magnitude by its nature is infinitely divisible, the result will be that each man will also have infinite sensations for each sensible object, infinite images, as it were, of the same thing in our ruling faculty.”
47 Ephrem the Syrian c. 306–373
Possekel [180]
48 Calcidius fl. c. 400
van Winden [241, p. 155]
49 Syrianus died c. 437
Wear [250]
Syrianus [57, p. 57]
50 Proclus 412–485
Opsomer [173] on the Elements of Physics
Morrow and Dillon [157]
Elements of Theology [58]
51 Irenaeus of Lyons c. 130–c. 202
Adversus haereses, II.1.4: “These remarks are, in like manner, applicable against the followers of Marcion. For his two gods will also be contained and circumscribed by an immense interval which separates them from one another. But then there is a necessity to suppose a multitude of gods separated by an immense distance from each other on every side, beginning with one another, and ending in one another.”
52 Clement of Alexandria c. 150–c. 215
Stromata
53 Hippolytus of Rome 170–235
Refutation of All Heresies, IV.51.
54 Origen 184/185–253/254
De Principiis
55 Alexander of Lycopolis fl. early fourth century
Infinite divisibility of matter [240]
56 Hilary of Poitiers c. 300–c. 368
De Trinitate. Meijering [151]
57 Basil the Great 329/330–379
Hexaemeron, Homily I, article 4: “These men who measure the distances of the stars and describe them, both those of the North, always shining brilliantly in our view, and those of the southern pole visible to the inhabitants of the South, but unknown to us; who divide the Northern zone and the circle of the Zodiac into an infinity of parts, who observe with exactitude the course of the stars, their fixed places, their declensions, their return and the time that each takes to make its revolution; these men, I say, have discovered all except one thing: the fact that God is the Creator of the universe, and the just Judge who rewards all the actions of life according to their merit.”
Hexaemeron, Homily I, article 6: “The beginning, in effect, is indivisible and instantaneous. The beginning of the road is not yet the road, and that of the house is not yet the house; so the beginning of time is not yet time and not even the least particle of it. If some objector tell us that the beginning is a time, he ought then, as he knows well, to submit it to the division of time – a beginning, a middle and an end. Now it is ridiculous to imagine a beginning of a beginning. Further, if we divide the beginning into two, we make two instead of one, or rather make several, we really make an infinity, for all that which is divided is divisible to the infinite.”
58 Gregory of Nyssa c. 335–c. 395
Against Eunomius, Book I. See entry for infinity in [144].
59 Augustine 354–430
Letter 3 (to Nebridius), article 3.
O’Daly [171, p. 157].
Knuutila [116]
De Trinitate, XI, article 17 and XV, chapter 12. In [146]
Confessions, book XI [9].
60 Themistius 317–c. 390
in Physicorum 91.29–30.
61 Simplicius
In Physicorum 139.27–140.6, Zeno’s arguments against plurality. See Curd [48, pp. 171–186]
Simplicius [238]
62 John Philoponus c. 490–c. 570
63 Olympiodorus
Furley [71]
64 Kalam
The kalam cosmological argument, in Craig and Sinclair [46]
Zimmerman [261]
Wolfson [259]
65 An-Nazzam c. 775–c. 846
Ibrahim An-Nazzam
66 Al-Kindi c. 801–c. 873
Al-Kindi [3]
67 ibn Qurra c. 826–901
Rashed [182]
68 Alfarabi c. 872–950/951
Alfarabi [139, pp. 101–111]
69 Al-Sijzi c. 945–c. 1020
Rashed [183]
70 Al-Biruni 973–1048
Letter to Avicenna: “If the sun is west of the moon in the sky, with a definite space between them, then even though the moon moves much faster than the sun, it should never be able to catch it. For the space between them can be conceived as divisible into an infinite number of parts; but how can a body moving with a finite speed cross an infinite number of spaces?” [200, p. 820]
71 Avicenna c. 980–1037
McGinnis [148]
Rashed [181]
72 Saint Anselm of Canterbury c. 1033 – 1109
, On the Incarnation of the Word, §15.
73 Al-Ghazali c. 1058–1111
Goodman [81]
74 Avempace c. 1085–1138
Lettinck [127]
75 Averroes 1126–1198
Glasner [77]
Goldstein [79]
76 Jewish philosophers
Saadia Gaon [186]
Maimonides, Guide for the Perplexed, I.73 106a
Rudavsky [189]
77 Gersonides 1288–1344
Gersonides [188]
Kohler [117]
78 Royal MS 4 A XIV, 12th century
Royal MS 4 A XIV, Against wens, ll. 11–13, Storms [216, p. 155, no. 4]: “May you become as small as a linseed grain,/ and much smaller than the hipbone of an itchmite,/and may you become so small that you become nothing.”
79 Peter Abelard 1079–1142
King [112, p. 94]
80 Hugh of Saint Victor c. 1096–1141
Didascalion, chapter 17: “From this consideration derives the axiom that continuous quantity is divisible into an infinite number of parts, and discrete quantity multipliable into a product of infinite size. For such is the vigor of the reason that it divides every length into lengths and every breadth into breadths, and the like – and that, to this same reason, a continuity lacking interruption continues forever.” [85, p. 58]
81 John of Salisbury
Metalogicon
82 William of Conches c. 1090–c. 1154
83 Herman of Carinthia c. 1100–c. 1160
De Essentiis [27, p. 252]
84 William of Auvergne 1180/1190–1249
William also presents arguments that the view that a continuum, such as time, is infinite results in paradoxes (OO I, 698a-700b).
William had read Aristotle’s Physics and agrees with Aristotle that time and motion are coextensive (OO I, 700a). Yet he does not propose Aristotle’s definition of time as the number of motion in respect of before and after. Rather, in his account of the essential nature of time he describes time simply as being that flows and does not last, “that is, it has nothing of itself that lasts in act or potency” (OO I, 683a; Teske [226, p. 102]), De universo.
85 Richard Rufus died c. 1260
Lewis [130]
86 Peter of Spain c. 1215-1277
Syncategoreumata [53], chapters 5 and 6
87 Roger Bacon c. 1214–c. 1292
Roger Bacon [85, p. 396]
In his Opus tertium, Opera quaedam hactenus inedita, cap 39, pp. 134–135, Roger Bacon writes:[63, p. 46]
A body’s potential for division cannot be reduced to actuality, purely and completely. It is a potentiality that one can only reduce to actuality impurely and incompletely, where there is always a mixture with a potential for further actualization; it is always reduced but in such a way that there remains the potential for another division. That is the potential of the continuum and that which constitutes infinite divisibility; when this potential is reduced by actual division, the possibility of another division is not excluded. Actually, it is required; in fact, the portion which is the result of divison is a magnitude; hence it is still divisible, and so forth to infinity.
Roger Bacon, Opus Majus, part 4, distinction 4, chapter IX [24, p. 173]: argues against the statement that “the world is composed of an infinite number of material particles called atoms, as Democritus and Leucippus maintained, by whose position Aristotle and all students of nature have been more hindered than by any other error”:
Yet this error is wholly eliminated by the power of geometry; for no stronger argument can be used against this error than that the diagonal of the square in that case and its side would be commensurable, that is, would have a common measure, namely, some aliquot part as a common measure, the contrary to which Aristotle always teaches. And the truth is clear by the demonstration from the last part of the seventh proposition of the tenth book of the Elements, where it is shown that if some measure, as a foot or a palm, measures the side, it will not measure the diagonal, nor vice versa; so that if the diagonal is ten feet, the side cannot be expressed exactly in feet. And not only does it follow from this position that they would be commensurable, but also equal. For if the side has ten atoms, or twelve, or more, then let the same number of lines be drawn from those atoms to the same number in the opposite side, the sides of the square being equal; wherefore just so many lines will occupy the whole surface of the square; and therefore since the diagonal passes through those lines, and no more can be drawn in the square, the diagonal must receive a single atom from each line, and therefore there will be no more atoms in the diagonal than in the side, and thus they have an aliquot part as a common measure, and the side has just as many parts as the diagonal, both of which conclusions are impossible.
88 Robert Grosseteste c. 1175–1253
89 Albertus Magnus c. 1200–1280
Twetten, Baldner, and Snyder [237]
Fox [66]
Money as infinitely divisible quantity [110]
90 Thomas Aquinas 1225–1274
Summa Theologica, prima pars, q. 7, article 3; q. 48, article 4; q. 53, article 2.
Commentaria in octo libros Physicorum, articles 69, 377–379 [7, pp. 188-189]
In libros De generatione et corruptione expositio, lecture 7, article 56; lecture 4, article 29.
91 Arnald Villanova c. 1240–1311
McVaugh on minima natura [150, p. 97]
92 Saint Bonaventure 1221–1274
93 Henry of Ghent c. 1217–1293
Brower-Toland [22]
94 Peter John Olivi
Pasnau [176]
95 Ramon Llull
Lohr [134]
96 Duns Scotus
Trifogli [233]
97 Godfrey of Fontaines
Dales [51, pp. 185–186, 202–203, 233, 255]
98 Henry of Harclay
Murdoch [165]
Dales [50]
99 Thomas Bradwardine
Dolnikowski [59]
100 Johannes de Muris
Busard [29, p. 35]. Porism to Prop. 19: “the horn-like angle is infinitely divisible by circular lines, can increase infinitely by diminishing the circles, and can decrease by augmenting the circles.”
101 Walter Chatton
Murdoch and Synan [161]
102 Gerardus Odonis c. 1285–1349
103 Nicolas Bonet
104 Nicholas of Autrecourt c. 1299–1369
The tniversal treatise.
105 Robert Kilwardby
Trifogli [234]
106 William of Auxerre
Tummers [236]
107 Peter of Auvergne
Galle [74, pp. 277*–330*]
108 John Buridan
Murdoch and Thijssen [162]
Buridan gives an example in his Quaestiones super octo libros Physicorum, lib. III, quaest. XVIII, fol. 63, col. d, about a cylindrical column dividied into proportional parts [63, p. 58]. In the same work, cols. c, d, Buridan writes “Assuredly, when I take my book, I take an infinity of parts of my book, for I am taking three parts, 100 parts, 1000 parts, and so forth without end. But what is impossible, is that one takes an infinity of parts successively, counting one after the other.”
109 Robert Holcot
A man is alternately meritorious and sinful in proportional parts of the last hour of his life. This suggests the geometric series
See Murdoch [164, p. 327]. It is from Holkot’s In quattuor libros Sententiarum quaestiones, book I, qu. 3, fol. Biiiiv, col. 2.
110 Aegidius Romanus
Porro [179]
Trifogli [231]
111 William Crathorn
112 Peter Auriol c. 1280–1322
113 William of Ockham
Goddu [78]
Murdoch [166]
114 John Bassolis
John Bassolis in his In Quatuor Sententiarum libros, Quaestiones in Primum Sententiarum, dist. XLIII, quaest. unica, fol. 213, col. c [63, p. 99]
The division of any finite quantity into parts whose magnitudes follow a constant relationship can be pursued to infinity. It is the same with the increase of a quantity by the addition of similar divisible parts. Divine virtue itself cannot reduce this division or this increase to actuality in facto esse, but only in fieri, and this is because the reality or nature of things repulses this actualization. But this in no way constitutes an objection to our proposition.
115 Richard of Middleton
Richard of Middleton in his commentary on Lombard’s Sentences Super quatuor libros Sententiarum Petri Lombardi quaestiones subtilissimae, lib. I, dist. XLIII, art. 1, quaest. IV, vol. 1, p. 386, col. b [63, p. 79]
When one states that any continuum is divisible to infinity, I reply that it is true as long as one understands it thus: It can be divided without end, but in such a way that the number of parts already obtained is always finite. If one admits that it is thus divided, no impossibility results; the existence of an infinite in facto esse does not result, only the existence of an infinite in fieri which one commonly calls an infinite in actuality mixed with potentiality.
116 William Heytesbury
Wilson [256]
Longeway [136]
117 Richard Kilvington
, Kretzmann and Kretzmann [121]
Jung and Podkoński [109]
118 John Dumbleton
119 Walter Burley
Duhem [63, p. 57] quotes from Walter Burley’s Super octo libros physicorum [221], lib. III, tract. II, cap. 4, fol. 70, col. b:
What we have just expounded upon proves the truth of the following proposition which is not known by many: Given any line, one can mark off segments whose lengths decrease proportionally, and one can also indicate a point which cannot be reached by a finite operation. That will occur if one takes as the first segment half the length to the extremity which cannot be reached by a finite operation; one takes as the second segment half the first segment, and so forth. On the other hand, every point before the extremity can be reached by a finite operation. That can easily be demonstrated geometrically, but for now we will not insist on its demonstration.
Spade [26, pp. 74–75, 117–123]
120 Albert of Saxony
Sarnowsky [194]
Biard [13]
121 Walter Odington
122 Richard Swineshead
123 Nicole Oresme
Questiones super Physicam [31]
124 Gregory of Rimini
Cross [47]
Thakkar [227]
Gregory of Rimini [230, p. 441], in the first conclusion of the first article on the first book of his commentary on the Sentences, says that “God can make any actually infinite multitude”, and gives the example of making an infinite number of angels in an hour, and talks about this using proportional parts: in each proportional part of an hour, God creates and preserves an angel, and at the end of the hour there are infinitely many angels. Rimini also talks about God creating an infinite magnitude [230, p. 445]. Also, creating infinity charity [230, pp. 446–447].
Gregory of Rimini in his In primum Sententiarum, dists. XLII, XLIII, XLIV, quaest. IV, art. 2, fol. 190, col. c (fol. 175, col. a) [63, pp. 115–116]:
When one says, infinity is something never completed, I reply that it is so if its infinitely numerous parts are acquired in equal durations; if, for example, each part of this infinity were acquired after an hour or a moment, or some other determined quantity of time. In that case, it would have to be that the time would have an infinity of equal parts and, consequently, that it would be infinite. Since, in any case, it is impossible that an infinite time whose first part is given becomes a past time, an infinity could not be totally completed or surpassed in this manner.
One says, infinity is something such that when one takes any part of it whatever, there always remains another part to be taken. I reply that this proposition must be understood as the previous one, by admitting that the parts taken successively are all of the same magnitude and that they are all taken in equal times. If one takes, in some time, a portion of infinity, then in a time equal to the one in which the first part was taken, one takes an equal portion, and one continues in this fashion, there will always remain something to be taken of this infinity, and it will never be taken in its totality….
But once equal parts of the infinity are not taken in equal times, but in times whose durations decrease in geometric progression… there is no longer any inconsistency in the infinity being taken in its totality, as long as there is no obstacle of some other nature to this. Similarly, there is no inconsistency in that the infinite multitude of parts of time, in which the successive parts of the infinite are taken, come to be completely past, as we have already stated. Not only is there no inconsistency in this, but it is necessary that it be.
Gregory of Rimini, responding to Zeno’s paradoxes as stated by writers such as Henricus Hibernicus, Adam Goddam, and Clienton Lengley, in his In secundum Sententiarum, dist. II, quaest. II, art. 1, fol. 34, col. c:[63, p. 57] “In any magnitude there is an infinity of proportional parts, infinity being taken syncategorematically; a result of this is that none of these parts is the last one.”
Duhem writes [63, p. 126] “it seems however that Oresme speaks the language of a disciple of Gregory of Rimini, of a defender of the categorematic infinite”. In his Traité du Ciel et du Monde, livre I, fol. 11, col. d (pp. 109–11), Nicole Oresme responds to Aristotle’s statement in De Caleo that an infinite body would have to be infinitely heavy: [63, p. 127]
But it seems to me that the reason given above is not evident without adding another assumption. For, in accordance with the second reply, I assume a body to be infinite, and I take or assign in this body a finite portion, spherical in shape, called . Next I take another sphere from the same section, and of the same shape, and then another sphere , exactly like and , proceeding in this manner without stopping. In this way, it appears that there are, in this infinite body, infinite equal parts , and so on without limit.
Now I posit that in the portion called there should be distributed the weight of one half-pound, and in there should likewise be distributed one-half of another half-pound, and in one-half of the residue of a pound, and in half of this remainder, which would be one-sixteenth part of a pound, and so on without end.
It appears then that the entire infinite body will weigh only one pound, while will weigh as much as all the other portions, however many, taken together.
125 Adam de Wodeham
Wood [260]
Courtenay [44]
126 Marsilius of Inghen
Hoenen [101]
127 Blasius of Parma
Biard [14]
128 Jean de Ripa
129 John Wycliffe c. 1331–1384
130 Patience
Eldredge [64]
131 John Dee
Clulee [38]
References
- [1] (1972) The nature of Zeno’s argument against plurality in DK 29 B 1. Phronesis 17 (1), pp. 40–52.
- [2] (2010) Some later medieval theories of the Eucharist: Thomas Aquinas, Giles of Rome, Duns Scotus, and William Ockham. Oxford University Press.
- [3] (2007) Al-kindi. Great Medieval Thinkers, Oxford University Press. Cited by: §66.
- [4] (1995) Concepts of space in Greek thought. Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy, Vol. LXV, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §8.
- [5] (1997) Plato’s Parmenides. revised edition, Yale University Press. Cited by: §16.
- [6] J. Annas and J. Barnes (Eds.) (2000) Sextus Empiricus: Outlines of Scepticism. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §40.
- [7] (1963) Commentary on Aristotle’s Physics. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. Note: Translated from the Latin by Richard J. Blackwell, Richard J. Spath, and W. Edmund Thirlkel Cited by: §90.
- [8] (2008) Physics. Oxford World’s Classics, Oxford University Press. Note: Translated by Robin Waterfield
- [9] (2009) Confessions. Oxford World’s Classics, Oxford University Press. Note: Translated from the Latin by Henry Chadwick Cited by: §59.
- [10] (2004) Greek musical writings, vol. II: harmonic and acoustic theory. Cambridge Readings in the Literature of Music, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §18.
- [11] (1982) The Presocratic philosophers. Arguments of the Philosophers, Routledge & Kegan Paul. Cited by: §1.
- [12] (2012) Sextus empiricus: Against the Physicists. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §40.
- [13] (1993) Albert de Saxe et les sophismes de l’infini. In Sophisms in Medieval Logic and Grammar, S. Read (Ed.), Nijhoff International Philosophy Series, Vol. 48, pp. 288–303. Cited by: §120.
- [14] (2009) Blasius of Parma facing atomist assumptions. In Atomism in Late Medieval Philosophy and Theology, C. Grellard and A. Robert (Eds.), pp. 221–234. Cited by: §127.
- [15] (1998) Sextus Empiricus: Against the grammarians. Clarendon Later Ancient Philosophers, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Cited by: §40.
- [16] (2001) Determinism and freedom in Stoic philosophy. Oxford University Press. Cited by: §29.
- [17] (1997) An approach to Aristotle’s physics. State University of New York Press. Cited by: §17.
- [18] (1972/1973) Aristotle, Zeno, and the potential infinite. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 73, pp. 37–51.
- [19] (1991) Aristotle on continuity in Physics VI. In Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays, L. Judson (Ed.), pp. 179–212.
- [20] (1959) The history of the calculus and its conceptual development. Dover Publications.
- [21] (2006) Cicero: On Academic Scepticism. Hackett Publishing Company. Cited by: §34.
- [22] (2002) Instantaneous change and the physics of sanctification: “quasi-Aristotelianism” in Henry of Ghent’s Quodlibet XV q. 13. Journal of the History of Philosophy 40 (1), pp. 19–46. Cited by: §93.
- [23] (1998) Walter Burley, Peter Aureoli and Gregory of Rimini. In Medieval Philosophy, J. Marenbon (Ed.), Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. 3, pp. 368–385.
- [24] (1928) The Opus Majus of Roger Bacon, volume I. University of Pennsylvania Press. Cited by: §87.
- [25] (1972) Lore and science in ancient Pythagoreanism. Harvard University Press. Note: Translated from the German by Edwin L. Minar, Jr. Cited by: §4.
- [26] (2000) On the purity of the art of logic: the shorter and longer treatises. Yale University Press. Note: Translated from the Latin by Paul Vincent Spade Cited by: §119.
- [27] (1982) Hermann of Carinthia De essentiis: a critical edition with translation and commentary. Studien und Texte Zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. 15, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §83.
- [28] (1984) The sceptic in his place and time. In Philosophy in History: Essays in the Historiography of Philosophy, R. Rorty, J. B. Schneewind, and Q. Skinner (Eds.), pp. 225–254.
- [29] (1998) Johannes de Muris, De arte mensurandi. Boethius, Vol. 41, Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart. Cited by: §100.
- [30] (1920) The purpose of Zeno’s arguments on motion. Isis 3 (1), pp. 7–20.
- [31] (2013) Nicole Oresme, Questiones super Physicam (Books I–VII). Studien und Texte Zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. 112, Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §123.
- [32] (1991) Aristotle’s potential infinities. In Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays, L. Judson (Ed.), pp. 129–149.
- [33] (1935) Aristotle’s criticism of Presocratic philosophy. Johns Hopkins University Press. Cited by: §17.
- [34] (1976) Plutarch’s Moralia, volume XIII, part II. Loeb Classical Library, Vol. 470, Harvard University Press. Cited by: §27.
- [35] (1965) On the possibility of completing an infinite process. The Philosophical Review 74 (1), pp. 74–87.
- [36] (1995) Aristotle and mathematics: aporetic method in cosmology and metaphysics. Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy, Vol. LXVII, E. J. Brill, Leiden.
- [37] (1965) The giants of pre-sophistic Greek philosophy: an attempt to reconstruct their thoughts. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Cited by: §43.
- [38] (2013) John Dee’s natural philosophy: between science and religion. Routledge. Cited by: §131.
- [39] (1997) Faith views the universe: a Thomistic perspective. University Press of America.
- [40] (2005) Time for Aristotle: Physics IV.10–14. Oxford Aristotle Studies, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
- [41] (1937) Plato’s cosmology: the Timaeus of Plato translated, with a running commentary. Kegan Paul, London. Cited by: §16.
- [42] (1964) Plato and Parmenides: Parmenides’ Way of Truth and Plato’s Parmenides translated with an introduction and a running commentary. Routledge & Kegan Paul, London. Cited by: §16.
- [43] (1991) From religion to philosophy: a study in the origins of Western speculation. Princeton University Press. Cited by: §16, §16, §6.
- [44] (1978) Adam Wodeham: an introduction to his life and writings. E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §125.
- [45] (2009) The fragments of Parmenides. Parmenides Publishing, Las Vegas. Note: Revised and expanded edition
- [46] (2012) The kalam cosmological argument. In The Blackwell Companion to Natural Theology, W. L. Craig and J. P. Moreland (Eds.), pp. 101–201. Cited by: §64.
- [47] (1998) Infinity, continuity, and composition: the contribution of Gregory of Rimini. Medieval Philosophy and Theology 7 (1), pp. 89–110. Cited by: §124.
- [48] (1998) The legacy of Parmenides: Eleatic monism and later Presocratic thought. Princeton University Press. Cited by: §61.
- [49] (2007) Anaxagoras of Clazomenae: fragments and testomonia. Phoenix Presocratics, Vol. 6, University of Toronto Press. Cited by: §9.
- [50] (1984) Henry of Harclay on the infinite. Journal for the History of Ideas 45 (2), pp. 295–301. Cited by: §98.
- [51] (1990) Medieval discussions of the eternity of the world. E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §97.
- [52] (1999) Measure of a different greatness: the intensive infinite, 1250–1650. Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. 67, Brill.
- [53] (1992) Peter of Spain (Petrus Hispanus Portugalensis): Syncategoreumata. Studien und Texte Zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. 30, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §86.
- [54] (1987) Archimedes. Princeton University Press. Note: Translated by C. Dikshoorn Cited by: §26.
- [55] (1977) The Middle Platonists, 80 B.C. to A.D. 220. revised edition, Cornell University Press. Cited by: §32.
- [56] (2003) The heirs of Plato: a study of the Old Academy (347–274 BC). Clarendon Press, Oxford. Cited by: §20, §34.
- [57] (2006) Syrianus: On Aristotle Metaphysics 13–14. Ancient Commentators on Aristotle, Bloomsbury. Cited by: §49.
- [58] (1963) Proclus: The elements of theology. second edition, Clarendon Press, Oxford. Cited by: §50.
- [59] (1995) Thomas Bradwardine: a view of time and a vision of eternity in fourteenth-century thought. Studies in the History of Christian Thought, Vol. 65, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §99.
- [60] (1972) Die Megariker: Kommentierte Sammlung der Testimonien. Studien zur antiken Philosophie, Vol. 2, B. R. Grüner N. V., Amsterdam.
- [61] (2008) In the beginning was the Apeiron: infinity in Greek philosophy. Palingenesia. Schriftenreihe fur Klassische Altertumswissenschaft, Vol. 94, Franz Steiner Verlag.
- [62] (1913) Études sur Léonard de Vinci, troisième série: Les précurseurs parisiens de Galilée. Librairie scientifique A. Hermann et fils, Paris.
- [63] (1985) Medieval cosmology: theories of infinity, place, time, void, and the plurality of worlds. University of Chicago Press. Note: Edited and translated by Roger Ariew, abridged from Le Système du monde Cited by: §108, §114, §115, §119, §124, §124, §124, §87.
- [64] (1979) Late medieval discussions of the continuum and the point of the Middle English Patience. Vivarium 17 (2), pp. 90–115. Cited by: §130.
- [65] (1996) The paradoxes of Zeno. Avebury Series in Philosophy, Avebury.
- [66] (2006) Time and eternity in mid-thirteenth-century thought. Oxford Theological Monographs, Oxford University Press. Cited by: §89.
- [67] (1946) The pre-Socratic philosophers. Basil Blackwell, Oxford.
- [68] (1983) Ancilla to the pre-Socratic philosophers. Harvard University Press. Cited by: §10, §12, §13, §7, §8.
- [69] (1973) Plato: an introduction. Princeton University Press. Note: Translated by Hans Meyerhoff Cited by: §16.
- [70] (1967) Two studies in the Greek atomists. Princeton University Press.
- [71] (1982) The Greek commentators’ treatment of Aristotle’s theory of the continuum. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 17–36. Cited by: §63.
- [72] (1998) Platons ungeschriebene Lehre. Studien zur systematischen und geschichtlichen Begründung der Wissenschaften in der Platonischen Schule. third edition, Klett-Cotta, Stuttgart. Cited by: §44.
- [73] (2003) Peter of Auvergne, Questions on Aristotle’s De caelo. Leuven University Press.
- [74] (2003) Peter of Auvergne: Questions on Aristotle’s De caelo. A critical edition with an interpretative essay. De Wulf-Mansion Centre, Ancient and Medieval Philosophy, Vol. XXIX, Leuven University Press. Cited by: §107.
- [75] (2000) Parmenides of Elea: fragments. Phoenix Presocratics, Vol. 1, University of Toronto Press. Cited by: §7.
- [76] (1995) The sea battle and the master argument: Aristotle and Diodorus Cronus on the metaphysics of the future. Quellen und Studien zur Philosophie, Vol. 40, Walter de Gruyter. Cited by: §25.
- [77] (2009) Averroes’ physics: a turning point in medieval natural philosophy. Oxford University Press. Cited by: §75.
- [78] (1984) The physics of william of ockham. Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. 16, Brill. Cited by: §113.
- [79] H. T. Goldstein (Ed.) (1991) Averroes’ questions in physics. The New Synthese Historical Library, Vol. 39, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Cited by: §75.
- [80] (1932) A neo-Pythagorean source in Philo Judaeus. In Yale Classical Studies, A. M. Harmon (Ed.), Vol. 3, pp. 115–164. Cited by: §37.
- [81] (1992) Time in Islam. In Religion and Time, A. N. Balslev and J. N. Mohanty (Eds.), Studies in the History of Religions, Vol. 54, pp. 138–162. Cited by: §73.
- [82] (1970) The philosophy of Chrysippus. Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Monographs on Ancient Philosophy, Vol. XVII, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §29.
- [83] (1972) Plotinus and the Stoics: a preliminary study. E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §42.
- [84] (1999) Empedocles and Anaxagoras: responses to Parmenides. In The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy, A. A. Long (Ed.), pp. 159–180.
- [85] E. Grant (Ed.) (1974) A source book in medieval science. Harvard University Press. Cited by: §80, §87.
- [86] (1969) Can an infinitude of operations be performed in a finite time?. British J. Philos. Sci. 20, pp. 203–218.
- [87] (1917) Numenius of Apamea, the father of neo-Platonism: works, biography, message, sources, and influence. George Bell and Sons, London. Cited by: §41.
- [88] (1987) The Pythagorean sourcebook and library. Phanes Press, Grand Rapids, MI. Cited by: §4.
- [89] (1965) A history of Greek philosophy, volume II: the Presocratic tradition from Parmenides to Democritus. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §8.
- [90] (1997) Continuum, infinity and analysis in theology. In Raum und Raumvorstellungen im Mittelalter, J. A. v. Aertsen and A. Speer (Eds.), Miscellanea Mediaevalia, Vol. 25, pp. 375–388.
- [91] (1995) The Sceptics. Arguments of the Philosophers, Routledge. Cited by: §40.
- [92] (2001) Cause and explanation in ancient Greek thought. Oxford University Press.
- [93] (1998) Physics and metaphysics in Hasdai Crescas. Amstedam Studies in Jewish Thought, Vol. 6, J. C. Gieben, Amsterdam. Cited by: §76.
- [94] (2006) Zeno unlimited. Oxford Studies in Ancient Philosophy 30, pp. 49–85.
- [95] (1897) The works of Archimedes. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §26.
- [96] (1921) A history of Greek mathematics, volume I. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Cited by: §3.
- [97] (1921) A history of Greek mathematics, volume II. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
- [98] (1949) Mathematics in Aristotle. Claredon Press, Oxford. Cited by: §17.
- [99] (2001) Void space, mathematical realism and Francesco Patrizi da Cherso’s use of atomistic arguments. In Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, C. Lüthy, J. E. Murdoch, and W. R. Newman (Eds.), Medieval and Early Modern Science, Vol. 1, pp. 133–161.
- [100] (1936) Aristotle. minor works. Loeb Classical Library, Vol. 307, Harvard University Press. Cited by: §17.
- [101] (1993) Marsilius of Inghen: divine knowledge in late medieval thought. E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §126.
- [102] (2013) Plato and Pythagoreanism. Oxford University Press. Cited by: §4.
- [103] (2005) Archtas of Tarentum: Pythagorean, philosopher and mathematician king. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §4.
- [104] (2006) Philolaus of Croton: Pythagorean and Presocratic. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §4.
- [105] (1997) Pythagoreans and Eleatics. In From the Beginning to Plato, C. C. W. Taylor (Ed.), Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. 1, pp. 117–160.
- [106] (1978) An interpretation of Zeno’s stadium paradox. Phronesis 23 (1), pp. 22–26.
- [107] (1997) Hellenistic philosophy: introductory readings. second edition, Hackett Publishing Company.
- [108] (1991) Aristotle on the reality of time. In Aristotle’s Physics: A Collection of Essays, L. Judson (Ed.), pp. 151–178.
- [109] (2009) Richard Kilvington on continuity. In Atomism in Late Medieval Philosophy and Theology, C. Grellard and A. Robert (Eds.), pp. 65–84. Cited by: §117.
- [110] (1998) Economy and nature in the fourteenth century: money, market exchange, and the emergence of scientific thought. Cambridge Studies in Medieval Life and Thought: Fourth Series, Vol. 35, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §89.
- [111] (1988) Posidonius, volume II. The commentary: i. Testimonia and fragments 1–149. Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries, Vol. 14a, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §35.
- [112] (2004) The metaphysics of Peter Abelard. In The Cambridge Companion to Abelard, J. E. Brower and K. Guilfoy (Eds.), pp. 65–125. Cited by: §79.
- [113] (1983) The Presocratic philosophers: a critical history with a selection of texts. second edition, Cambridge University Press.
- [114] (1982) Infinity and continuity: the interaction of mathematics and philosophy in antiquity. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 112–145.
- [115] (1979) Plato in infinitum remisse incipit esse albus. In Essays in Honour of Jaakko Hintikka, E. Saarinen, R. Hilpinen, I. Niiniluoto, and M. P. Hintikka (Eds.), Synthese Library, Vol. 124, pp. 309–329.
- [116] (2014) Time and creation in Augustine. In The Cambridge Companion to Augustine, D. V. Meconi and E. Stump (Eds.), pp. 81–97. Cited by: §59.
- [117] (2006) Medieval infinities in mathematics and the contribution of Gersonides. History of Philosophy Quarterly 23 (2), pp. 95–116. Cited by: §77.
- [118] (1983) Problems in Epicurean physics. In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, volume II, J. P. Anton and A. Preus (Eds.), pp. 431–464.
- [119] D. Konstan (Ed.) (2014) Simplicius: On Aristotle Physics 6. Ancient Commentators on Aristotle, Bloomsbury.
- [120] (1995) Aristotle on mathematical infinity. Palingenesia, Vol. 58, Franz Steiner Verlag, Stuttgart.
- [121] (1990) The sophismata of Richard Kilvington. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §117.
- [122] (1982) Continuity, contrariety, contradiction, and change. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 270–296.
- [123] H. Lagerlund (Ed.) (2011) Encyclopedia of medieval philosophy: philosophy between 500 and 1500. Springer.
- [124] (1981) A note on Zeno’s arrow. Phronesis 26 (2), pp. 91–104.
- [125] (1936) Zeno of Elea; a text, with translation and notes. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §8.
- [126] (1992) Xenophanes of Colophon: fragments. Phoenix Presocratics, Vol. 4, University of Toronto Press. Cited by: §5.
- [127] (1994) Aristotle’s Physics and its reception in the Arabic world. Aristoteles Semitico-Latinus, Vol. 7, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §74.
- [128] (2009) Greek reflections on the nature of music. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §18.
- [129] (2005) Robert Grosseteste and the continuum. In Albertus Magnus und die Anfänge der Aristoteles-Rezeption im lateinischen Mittelalter, Ludger, Honnefelder, R. Wood, M. Dreyer, and M. Aris (Eds.), pp. 159–188. Cited by: §88.
- [130] (2012) Robert Grosseteste and Richard Rufus of Cornwall on unequal infinites. In Robert Grosseteste: His Thought and Its Impact, J. P. Cunningham (Ed.), pp. 227–256. Cited by: §85, §88.
- [131] (1966) Polarity and analogy: two types of argumentation in early Greek thought. Cambridge University Press.
- [132] (1968) Plato as a natural scientist. Journal of Hellenic Studies 88, pp. 78–92.
- [133] (1979) Magic, reason and experience: studies in the origin and development of Greek science. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §8.
- [134] (2001) Ramon Lull’s theory of the continuous and discrete. In Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, C. Lüthy, J. E. Murdoch, and W. R. Newman (Eds.), Medieval and Early Modern Science, Vol. 1, pp. 75–90. Cited by: §95.
- [135] (1987) The Hellenistic philosophers. Volume 1: translations of the principal sources, with philosophical commentary. Cambridge University Press.
- [136] (1984) William Heytesbury, On maxima and minima. Chapter 5 of Rules for solving sophismata, with an anonymous fourteenth-century discussion. Synthese Historical Library, Vol. 26, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht. Cited by: §116.
- [137] (2009) On the nature of the universe. Oxford World’s Classics, Oxford University Press. Note: Translated from the Latin by Ronald Melville Cited by: §36.
- [138] (1932) Die Infinitesimaltheorie der antike Atomisten. Quellen und Studien zur Geschichte der Mathematik, Abteilung B 2, pp. 106–185. Cited by: §10.
- [139] (2001) Alfarabi’s philosophy of Plato and Aristotle. revised edition, Cornell University Press. Cited by: §68.
- [140] (1949) Die Vorläufer Galileis im 14. Jahrhundert. Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, Rome. Note: Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, 1. Band
- [141] (1952) An der Grenze von Scholastik und Naturwissenschaft. second edition, Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, Rome. Note: Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, 3. Band
- [142] (1968) Zwei Grundprobleme der scholastischen Naturphilosophie. third edition, Edizioni di Storia e Letteratura, Rome. Note: Studien zur Naturphilosophie der Spätscholastik, 2. Band
- [143] F. A. C. Mantello and A. G. Rigg (Eds.) (1996) Medieval latin: an introduction and bibliographical guide. The Catholic University of America Press.
- [144] L. F. Mateo-Seco and G. Maspero (Eds.) (2009) The Brill dictionary of Gregory of Nyssa. Supplements to Vigiliae Christianae, Vol. 99, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §58.
- [145] (2001) Zeno moves!. In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy VI: Before Plato, A. Preus (Ed.), pp. .
- [146] G. B. Matthews (Ed.) (2002) Augustine: On the Trinity, Books 8–15. Cambridge Texts in the History of Philosophy, Cambridge University Press. Note: Translated by Stephen McKenna Cited by: §59.
- [147] (2007) Classical Arabic philosophy: an anthology of sources. Hackett Publishing.
- [148] (2010) Avicenna. Great Medieval Thinkers, Oxford University Press. Cited by: §71.
- [149] (1999) Parmenides and Melissus. In The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy, A. A. Long (Ed.), pp. 134–158.
- [150] M. R. McVaugh (Ed.) (1975) Arnaldi de Villanova Opera medica omnia, II: Aphorismi de gradibus. Universitat de Barcelona. Cited by: §91.
- [151] (1982) Hilary of Poitiers on the Trinity: De Trinitate 1, 1-19, 2, 3. Philosophia Patrum, Vol. 6, E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §56.
- [152] (2015) What’s location got to do with it? Place, space, and the infinite in classical Greek mathematics. In Mathematizing Space: The Objects of Geometry from Antiquity to the Early Modern Age, V. D. Risi (Ed.), Trends in the History of Science, pp. 15–64.
- [153] (1982) Aristotle against the atomists. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 87–111.
- [154] (2002) The limitations of ancient atomism. In Science and Mathematics in Ancient Greek Culture, C. J. Tuplin and T. E. Rihll (Eds.), Cited by: §28.
- [155] (2001) Roger Bacon’s corpuscular tendencies (and some of Grosseteste’s too). In Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, C. Lüthy, J. E. Murdoch, and W. R. Newman (Eds.), Medieval and Early Modern Science, Vol. 1, pp. 57–73.
- [156] (2002) On location: Aristotle’s concept of place. Oxford Aristotle Studies, Clarendon Press, Oxford.
- [157] G. R. Morrow and J. M. Dillon (Eds.) (1987) Proclus’ Commentary on Plato’s Parmenides. Princeton University Press. Cited by: §50.
- [158] (1970) The route of Parmenides. Yale University Press. Cited by: §7.
- [159] (1982) Aristotle and the quadrature of the circle. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 146–164.
- [160] (1997) Greek arithmetic, geometry and harmonics: Thales to Plato. In From the Beginning to Plato, C. C. W. Taylor (Ed.), Routledge History of Philosophy, Vol. 1, pp. 249–297.
- [161] (1966) Two questions on the continuum: Walter Chatton (?), O.F.M. and Adam Wodeham, O.F.M.. Franciscan Studies 26 (1), pp. 212–288. Cited by: §101.
- [162] (2000) John Buridan on infinity. In The Metaphysics and Natural Philosophy of John Buridan, J. M. M. H. Thijssen and J. Zupko (Eds.), Medieval and Early Modern Science, Vol. 2, pp. 127–150. Cited by: §108.
- [163] (1963) The medieval language of proportions: elements of the interaction with Greek foundations and the development of new mathematical techniques. In Scientific Change, A. C. Crombie (Ed.),
- [164] (1975) From social into intellectual factors: an aspect of the unitary character of late medieval learning. In The Cultural Context of Medieval Learning, J. E. Murdoch and E. D. Sylla (Eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 26, pp. 271–348. Cited by: §109.
- [165] (1981) Henry of Harclay and the infinite. In Studi sul XIV secolo in memoria di Anneliese Maier, A. P. Bagliani and A. Maierú (Eds.), pp. 219–261. Cited by: §98.
- [166] (1982) William of Ockham and the logic of infinity and continuity. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 165–207. Cited by: §113.
- [167] (2001) The medieval and Renaissance tradition of minima naturalia. In Late Medieval and Early Modern Corpuscular Matter Theories, C. Lüthy, J. E. Murdoch, and W. R. Newman (Eds.), Medieval and Early Modern Science, Vol. 1, pp. 91–131.
- [168] (2009) Beyond Aristotle: indivisibles and infinite divisibility in the later Middle Ages. In Atomism in Late Medieval Philosophy and Theology, C. Grellard and A. Robert (Eds.), pp. 15–38.
- [169] (1993) An introduction to Islamic cosmological doctrines. State University of New York Press.
- [170] (1982) Walter Burley on continuity. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 258–269.
- [171] (1987) Augustine’s philosophy of mind. University of California Press. Cited by: §59.
- [172] (1989) Pythagoras revived: mathematics and philosophy in late antiquity. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
- [173] (2009) The integration of Aristotelian physics in a Neoplatonic context: Proclus on movers and divisibility. In Physics and Philosophy of Nature in Greek Neoplatonism, R. Chiaradonna and F. Trabattoni (Eds.), Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy, Vol. 115, pp. 189–229. Cited by: §50.
- [174] (1957–1958) Zeno and the mathematicians. Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 58, pp. 199–222.
- [175] (2009) Parmenides and Presocratic philosophy. Oxford University Press. Cited by: §7.
- [176] (2011) Metaphysical themes 1274–1671. Oxford University Press. Cited by: §94.
- [177] (2002) Antiphon the Sophist: the fragments. Cambridge Classical Texts and Commentaries, Vol. 39, Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §14.
- [178] (2007) Aristotle’s De anima: a critical commentary. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §17.
- [179] (2001) Angelic measures: Aevum and discrete time. In The Medieval Concept of Time: The Scholastic Debate and its Reception in Early Modern Philosophy, P. Porro (Ed.), Studien und Texte Zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. 75, pp. 131–160. Cited by: §110.
- [180] (1999) Evidence of Greek philosophical concepts in the writings of Ephrem the Syrian. Corpus Scriptorum Christianorum Orientalium, Vol. 580, Peeters Publishers, Louvain. Cited by: §47.
- [181] (2005) Natural philosophy. In The Cambridge Companion to Arabic Philosophy, P. Adamson and R. C. Taylor (Eds.), pp. 287–307. Cited by: §71.
- [182] (2009) Thābit ibn Qurra, la Physique d’Aristote et le meilleur des mondes. In Thābit ibn Qurra: Science and Philosophy in Ninth-Century Baghdad, R. Rashed (Ed.), pp. 675–714. Cited by: §67.
- [183] (2000) Al-sijzī and maimonides: a mathematical and philosophical commentary on Proposition II–14 in Apollonius’ Conic Sections. In Maimonides and the Sciences, R. S. Cohen and H. Levine (Eds.), Boston Studies in the Philosophy of Science, Vol. 211, pp. 159–172. Cited by: §69.
- [184] (1948) Pythagoreans and Eleatics. Cambridge University Press.
- [185] (2011) Aristotle on time: a study of the Physics. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §17.
- [186] (1948) Saadia Gaon, The Book of Beliefs and Opinions. Yale Judaica Series, Vol. 1, Yale University Press. Cited by: §76.
- [187] (1966) Aristotle. fifth edition, Methuen, London. Cited by: §17.
- [188] (1988) Creation, time and infinity in Gersonides. Journal of the History of Philosophy 26 (1), pp. 25–44. Cited by: §77.
- [189] (2000) Time matters: time, creation, and cosmology in medieval Jewish philosophy. State University of New York Press. Cited by: §76.
- [190] (2004) The forgotten revolution. Springer. Note: Translated from the Italian by Silvio Levy
- [191] (1959) Physics of the Stoics. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London. Cited by: §20.
- [192] (1962) The physical world of late antiquity. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
- [193] (1963) The physical world of the Greeks. Routledge and Kegan Paul, London.
- [194] (1989) Die aristotelisch-scholastische Theorie der Bewegung. Studien zum Kommentar Alberts von Sachsen zur Physik des Aristoteles. Beiträge zur Geschichte der Philosophie und Theologie des Mittelalters. Neue Folge, Vol. 32, Aschendorff, Münster. Cited by: §120.
- [195] (1980) An essay on Anaxagoras. Cambridge University Press. Cited by: §9.
- [196] (1977) Diodorus Cronus and Hellenistic philosophy. Proceedings of the Cambridge Philological Society (New Series) 23, pp. 74–120.
- [197] (1999) Parmenides and Melissus. In The Cambridge Companion to Early Greek Philosophy, A. A. Long (Ed.), pp. 113–133.
- [198] (2001) The origins of Stoic God. In Traditions of Theology: Studies in Hellenistic Theology, its Background and Aftermath, D. Frede and A. Laks (Eds.), Philosophia Antiqua, Vol. 89, pp. 41–84. Cited by: §33.
- [199] (2004) On generation and corruption i.2. In Aristotle’s On generation and corruption I, F. d. Haas and J. Mansfeld (Eds.), Symposium Aristotelicum, pp. 65–90.
- [200] H. Selin (Ed.) (2008) Encyclopaedia of the history of science, technology, and medicine in non-western cultures. Springer. Cited by: §70.
- [201] (1992) Alexander of Aphrodisias Quaestiones 1.1–2.15. Duckworth, London. Cited by: §38.
- [202] (1994) Alexander of Aphrodisias Quaestiones 2.16–3.15. Duckworth, London. Cited by: §38.
- [203] (1998) Theophrastus of Eresus: sources for his life, writings, thought and influence. Commentary, volume 3.1: sources on physics. Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Studies on Ancient Philosophy, Vol. LXXIX, Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §21.
- [204] (2002) Eudemus’ Physics: change, place and time. In Eudemus of Rhodes, I. Bodnár and W. F. Fortenbaugh (Eds.), Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities, Vol. XI, pp. 107–126. Cited by: §24.
- [205] (2009) “Unjointed masses”: a note on Heraclides’ physical theory. In Heraclides of Pontus: Discussion, W. W. Fortenbaugh and E. Pender (Eds.), Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities, Vol. XV, pp. 139–154. Cited by: §19.
- [206] (2011) Strato of Lampsacus: the sources, texts and translations. In Strato of Lampsacus: Text, Translation, and Discussion, M. Desclos and W. W. Fortenbaugh (Eds.), Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities, Vol. XVI, pp. 5–229. Cited by: §23.
- [207] (2012) “Praxiphanes of Rhodes held the same opinions as Theophrastus” (Epiphanius, De fide 9.38). In Praxiphanes of Mytilene and Chamaeleon of Heraclea: Text, Translation, and Discussion, A. Martano, E. Matelli, and D. Mirhady (Eds.), Rutgers University Studies in Classical Humanities, Vol. XVIII, pp. 463–476. Cited by: §22.
- [208] (1985) A history of Jewish philosophy in the middle ages. Cambridge University Press.
- [209] (1960) The discovery of the mind: the Greek origins of European thought. Harper, New York. Note: Translated from the German by T. G. Rosenmeyer Cited by: §2.
- [210] (1960) Aristotle’s system of the physical world: a comparison with his predecessors. Cornell University Press.
- [211] (1975) Intellectual experiments of the Greek Enlightenment. Princeton University Press. Cited by: §8.
- [212] (1982) Time and time atoms. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 37–86.
- [213] (1983) Time, creation and the continuum: theories in antiquity and the Early Middle Ages. University of Chicago Press.
- [214] R. Sorabji (Ed.) (2004) The philosophy of the commentators, 200–600 AD. A sourcebook. Volume 2. Physics. Duckworth, London.
- [215] (1982) Quasi-Aristotelianism. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 297–307.
- [216] (1949) Anglo-Saxon magic. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague. Cited by: §78.
- [217] (1982) Theology and physics in De sacramento altaris: Ockham’s theory of indivisibles. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 207–230.
- [218] (1972) Infinity in the Presocratics: a bibliographical and philosophical study. Martinus Nijhoff, The Hague.
- [219] (1992) Divine infinity in Greek and medieval thought. Peter Lang, New York.
- [220] (1982) Infinite indivisibles and continuity in fourteenth-century theories of alteration. In Infinity and Continuity in Ancient and Medieval Thought, N. Kretzmann (Ed.), pp. 231–257.
- [221] (2001) Walter Burley’s Physics commentaries and the mathematics of alteration. Early Science and Medicine 6 (3), pp. 149–184. Cited by: §119.
- [222] (1978) The beginnings of Greek mathematics. Sythese Historical Library, Vol. 17, D. Reidel Publishing Company, Dordrecht. Note: Translated from the German by A. M. Ungar Cited by: §3.
- [223] (2003) Byzantine philosophy. Hackett Publishing Company. Note: Translated by Nicholas J. Moutafakis
- [224] (2013) Plato: the man and his work. fourth edition, Routledge. Cited by: §16.
- [225] (2010) The Atomists: Leucippus and Democritus. Fragments. Phoenix Presocratics, Vol. 5, University of Toronto Press. Cited by: §10.
- [226] (1998) William of Auvergne: The universe of creatures. Mediaeval Philosophical Texts in Translation, Marquette University Press. Cited by: §84.
- [227] (2009) Mathematics in fourteenth-century theology. In The Oxford Handbook of the History of Mathematics, E. Robson and J. Stedall (Eds.), pp. 619–638. Cited by: §124.
- [228] (1973) Chrysippus on infinite divisibility (Diogenes Laertius VII.150). Apeiron 7 (1), pp. 21–29.
- [229] (1976) Alexander of Aphrodisias on Stoic physics: a study of the De mixtione with preliminary essays, text, translation and commentary. Philosophia Antiqua: A Series of Monographs on Ancient Philosophy, Vol. XXVIII, E. J. Brill, Leiden.
- [230] A. D. Trapp and V. Marcolino (Eds.) (1984) Gregorii Ariminensis OESA Lectura super primum et secundum Sententiarum, tomus III: Super primum (Dist. 19–48). Walter de Gruyter. Cited by: §124.
- [231] (1993) Giles of Rome on the instant of change. Synthese 96 (1), pp. 93–114. Cited by: §110.
- [232] (2000) Oxford physics in the thirteenth century (ca. 1250–1270): motion, infinity, place and time. Studien und Texte zur Geistesgeschichte des Mittelalters, Vol. LXXII, Brill, Leiden.
- [233] (2004) Duns Scotus and the medieval debate about the continuum. Medioevo 24, pp. 233–266. Cited by: §96.
- [234] (2012) Robert Kilwardby on time. In A Companion to the Philosophy of Robert Kilwardby, H. Lagerlund and P. Thom (Eds.), Brill’s Companions to the Christian Tradition, Vol. 37, pp. 209–238. Cited by: §105.
- [235] (2013) Motion and time. In A Companion to Walter Burley: Late Medieval Logician and Metaphysician, A. Conti (Ed.), Brill’s Companions to the Christian Tradition, Vol. 41, pp. 267–300.
- [236] (1980) Geometry and theology in the XIIIth century: an example of their interrelation as found in the Ms Admont 442. The influence of William of Auxerre?. Vivarium 18 (2), pp. 112–142. Cited by: §106.
- [237] (2013) Albert’s physics. In A Companion to Albert the Great: Theology, Philosophy, and the Sciences, I. Resnick (Ed.), pp. 173–219. Cited by: §89.
- [238] (2014) Simplicius: Corollaries on place and time. Ancient Commentators on Aristotle, Bloomsbury. Cited by: §61.
- [239] (1990) The lost theory of Asclepiades of Bithynia. Clarendon Press, Oxford. Cited by: §31.
- [240] (1974) An Alexandrian Platonist against dualism: Alexander of Lycopolis’ treatise ‘Critique of the doctrines of Manichaeus’. E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §55.
- [241] (1965) Calcidius on matter: his doctrine and sources. E. J. Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §48.
- [242] (1965) Minimal parts in Epicurean atomism. Isis 56 (2), pp. 121–147. Cited by: §28.
- [243] (1966) A note on Zeno’s Arrow. Phronesis 11 (1), pp. 3–18.
- [244] (1966) Zeno’s race course. Journal of the History of Philosophy 4 (2), pp. 95–108.
- [245] (1971) A Zenonian argument against plurality. In Essays in Ancient Greek Philosophy, J. P. Anton and G. L. Kustas (Eds.), pp. 119–144.
- [246] (1996) Plotinus on the nature of physical reality. In The Cambridge Companion to Plotinus, L. P. Gerson (Ed.), pp. 130–170. Cited by: §42.
- [247] (1972) Neoplatonism. Duckworth, London. Cited by: §42.
- [248] (1988) Iamblichus: The Theology of Arithmetic. Phanes Press, Grand Rapids, MI. Cited by: §45.
- [249] (2009) The first philosophers: the Presocratics and Sophists. Oxford World’s Classics, Oxford University Press. Cited by: §8.
- [250] (2011) The teachings of Syrianus on Plato’s Timaeus and Parmenides. Ancient Mediterranean and Medieval Texts and Contexts: Studies in Platonism, Neoplatonism, and the Platonic Tradition, Vol. 10, Brill, Leiden. Cited by: §49.
- [251] (1955) Die Schule des Aristoteles: Texte und Kommentar. Heft VIII: Eudemos von Rhodos. Benno Schwabe & Co., Basel. Cited by: §24.
- [252] (1992) The continuous and the discrete: ancient physical theories from a contemporary perspective. Clarendon Press, Oxford.
- [253] (2003) Stoic natural philosophy (physics and cosmology). In The Cambridge Companion to the Stoics, B. Inwood (Ed.), pp. 124–152.
- [254] (1976) Philological comments on the Neoplatonic notion of infinity. In The Significance of Neoplatonism, R. B. Harris (Ed.), Studies in Neoplatonism, Vol. 1, pp. 155–172. Cited by: §42.
- [255] (1987) Philoponus: Against Aristotle, on the eternity of the world. Ancient Commentators on Aristotle, Duckworth.
- [256] (1956) William of Heytesbury: medieval logic and the rise of mathematical physics. University of Wisconsin Publications in Medieval Science, Vol. 3, University of Wisconsin Press. Cited by: §116.
- [257] (1999) The metaphysical thought of Godfrey of Fontaines: a study in late thirteenth-century philosophy. The Catholic University of America Press.
- [258] (1929) Crescas’ critique of Aristotle: problems of Aristotle’s Physics in Jewish and Arabic philosophy. Harvard Semitic Series, Vol. VI, Harvard University Press. Cited by: §76.
- [259] (1976) The philosophy of the Kalam. Structure and Growth of Philosophic Systems from Plato to Spinoza, Vol. IV, Harvard University Press. Cited by: §64.
- [260] (1988) Adam de Wodeham: Tractatus de indivisibilibus. A critical edition with introduction, translation, and textual notes. Synthese Historical Library, Vol. 31, Kluwer Academic Publishers. Cited by: §125.
- [261] (2014) Kalām and the Greeks. In Islamic Cultures, Islamic Contexts: Essays in Honor of Professor Patricia Crone, A. Q. Ahmed, B. Sadeghi, R. G. Hoyland, and A. Silverstein (Eds.), Islamic History and Civilization, Vol. 114, pp. 343–363. Cited by: §64.